9780792324751-0792324757-The Completeness of Scientific Theories: On the Derivation of Empirical Indicators within a Theoretical Framework: The Case of Physical Geometry (The ... Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science, 53)

The Completeness of Scientific Theories: On the Derivation of Empirical Indicators within a Theoretical Framework: The Case of Physical Geometry (The ... Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science, 53)

ISBN-13: 9780792324751
ISBN-10: 0792324757
Edition: 1994
Author: Martin Carrier
Publication date: 1993
Publisher: Kluwer Academic Publishers
Format: Hardcover 296 pages
FREE US shipping on ALL non-marketplace orders
Marketplace
from $125.00 USD
Buy

From $125.00

Book details

ISBN-13: 9780792324751
ISBN-10: 0792324757
Edition: 1994
Author: Martin Carrier
Publication date: 1993
Publisher: Kluwer Academic Publishers
Format: Hardcover 296 pages

Summary

The Completeness of Scientific Theories: On the Derivation of Empirical Indicators within a Theoretical Framework: The Case of Physical Geometry (The ... Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science, 53) (ISBN-13: 9780792324751 and ISBN-10: 0792324757), written by authors Martin Carrier, was published by Kluwer Academic Publishers in 1993. With an overall rating of 4.4 stars, it's a notable title among other books. You can easily purchase or rent The Completeness of Scientific Theories: On the Derivation of Empirical Indicators within a Theoretical Framework: The Case of Physical Geometry (The ... Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science, 53) (Hardcover) from BooksRun, along with many other new and used books and textbooks. And, if you're looking to sell your copy, our current buyback offer is $0.3.

Description

Earlier in this century, many philosophers of science (for example, Rudolf Carnap) drew a fairly sharp distinction between theory and observation, between theoretical terms like 'mass' and 'electron', and observation terms like 'measures three meters in length' and 'is _2° Celsius'. By simply looking at our instruments we can ascertain what numbers our measurements yield. Creatures like mass are different: we determine mass by calculation; we never directly observe a mass. Nor an electron: this term is introduced in order to explain what we observe. This (once standard) distinction between theory and observation was eventually found to be wanting. First, if the distinction holds, it is difficult to see what can characterize the relationship between theory :md observation. How can theoretical terms explain that which is itself in no way theorized? The second point leads out of the first: are not the instruments that provide us with observational material themselves creatures of theory? Is it really possible to have an observation language that is entirely barren of theory? The theory-Iadenness of observation languages is now an accept ed feature of the logic of science. Many regard such dependence of observation on theory as a virtue. If our instruments of observation do not derive their meaning from theories, whence comes that meaning? Surely - in science - we have nothing else but theories to tell us what to try to observe.

Rate this book Rate this book

We would LOVE it if you could help us and other readers by reviewing the book